An ecosystem's complexity develops from the vast numbers of species interacting in ecological communities. The nature of these interactions, in turn, depends on environmental context. How do these components together influence an ecosystem's behavior as a whole? Can ecologists resolve an ecosystem's complexity in order to predict its response to disturbances? Resolving Ecosystem Complexity develops a framework for anticipating the ways environmental context determines the functioning of ecosystems.
Oswald Schmitz addresses the critical questions of contemporary ecology: How should an ecosystem be conceptualized to blend its biotic and biophysical components? How should evolutionary ecological principles be used to derive an operational understanding of complex, adaptive ecosystems? How should the relationship between the functional biotic diversity of ecosystems and their properties be understood? Schmitz begins with the universal concept that ecosystems are comprised of species that consume resources and which are then resources for other consumers. From this, he deduces a fundamental rule or evolutionary ecological mechanism for explaining context dependency: individuals within a species trade off foraging gains against the risk of being consumed by predators. Through empirical examples, Schmitz illustrates how species use evolutionary ecological strategies to negotiate a predator-eat-predator world, and he suggests that the implications of species trade-offs are critical to making ecology a predictive science.
Bridging the traditional divides between individuals, populations, and communities in ecology, Resolving Ecosystem Complexity builds a systematic foundation for thinking about natural systems.
"synopsis" may belong to another edition of this title.
Oswald J. Schmitz is the Oastler Professor of Population and Community Ecology in the Yale School of Forestry and Environmental Studies.
"Resolving Ecosystem Complexity presents a modern synthesis of trophic structure and function that addresses some of the most fundamental questions raised by Darwin, Tansley, and Hutchinson. Through rigorous analysis of case studies and data, Schmitz brings to life the importance of direct and indirect interactions on the functioning of ecosystems. This clear and compelling book is a must-read for scientists and educators interested in integrative ecosystem analysis."--Adrien Finzi, Boston University
"This ambitious and inspiring book is a valuable contribution to ecology. Highly synthetic, it melds an overall approach to science with summaries of detailed empirical and theoretical work. Resolving Ecosystem Complexity is remarkably well done and I learned a great deal from reading this important book."--Anurag Agrawal, Cornell University
"This book focuses on the importance of multitrophic interactions in ecology. It illuminates significant points and helped me to think about complex ecosystems more clearly."--Frederick R. Adler, University of Utah
List of Illustrations..............................................................ixList of Tables.....................................................................xiiiPreface............................................................................xv1. Introduction....................................................................12. Conceptualizing Ecosystem Structure.............................................103. Trophic Dynamics: Why Is the World Green?.......................................234. The Green World and the Brown Chain.............................................555. The Evolutionary Ecology of Trophic Control in Ecosystems.......................686. The Whole and the Parts.........................................................997. The Ecological Theater and the Evolutionary Ecological Play.....................125Closing Remarks....................................................................139References.........................................................................143Index..............................................................................167
Ecosystems are paradigmatically among the most complex systems known to science. They contain many different components (e.g., individuals within species populations, species within communities) interacting directly and indirectly in highly interconnected networks (Paine 1980; Schoener 1993; Brown 1995; Yodzis 1995; Levin 1998; Cohen et al. 1990). Moreover, system properties such as trophic structure and functions such as nutrient fluxes and productivity emerge from direct and indirect interactions among the component parts (Brown 1995; Levin 1998). This feature of ecosystems fascinates those who have purely academic interests to develop broad theoretical principles that explain the emergence of complexity (e.g., Holland 1992; Cowan, Pines, and Meltzer 1994; Gell-Mann 1994; Brak 1996; Milo et al. 2002). Complexity theorists, however, treat ecosystems merely as powerful metaphors and accordingly abstract much ecological detail (e.g., treating species as nodes in a network abstracts species' functional traits) to facilitate pattern identification and comparison among myriad physical, chemical, biological, social, and economic systems.
Ecologists too have a fundamental academic interest in resolving ecological complexity (e.g., May 1973; O'Neill et al. 1986; MacMahon et al. 1987; Allen and Hoekstra 1992; Levin 1992, 1998; Turchin 2003). But, that academic interest is tempered by the important practical reality that ecology is increasingly being called upon to offer a leading role in identifying and solving pressing environmental problems (Worster 1994; Lubchenco et al. 1991; Levin 1999; Ludwig, Mangel, and Haddad 2001). There is a huge premium, then, to resolve complexity in ways that enable one to make general predictions about how ecosystems will function in response to myriad natural and human-caused disturbances. Making reliable predictions requires having a solid empirical understanding of how the components fit together to determine whole ecosystem functioning. In this endeavor, ecologists must, to some extent, embrace ecological details because they provide the contexts for discovering the mechanisms leading to different outcomes. The challenge, then, is to develop an empirical research program that can resolve what mechanisms must be understood in order to predict the different outcomes (Levin 1992). This book elaborates such an empirical program.
PHILOSOPHICAL MUSINGS
Ecologists do not rely on a single empirical method to derive understanding of their systems (Hairston 1990). Broadly speaking, they use two different kinds of approaches: experimentation (Hairston 1990) and meta-analyses (Peters 1986; Hedges, Gurevitch, and Curtis 1999; Osenberg, Sarnelle, and Cooper 1999). Experimentation is believed to lead to predictive insights because it uncovers causal relationships (Lehman 1986). Meta-analysis is believed to offer predictive insights whenever the function that is statistically fit to the data explains a good degree of variation in the data set (Peters 1986). These different approaches lead to different understanding of the relationship between the whole system and its component parts and ultimately on the application of that knowledge to solve environmental problems (Lehman 1986; Lawton 1999). Let me illustrate my point with an example.
Suppose we agreed that a reasonable way to characterize ecosystems is by their component plant species and the plant species' trophic linkages with the soil nutrient pool. Suppose that ultimately we wanted to predict how the number of plant species (a measure of plant species diversity) influenced the level of some ecosystem function such as nutrient cycling or primary production. We might then manipulate plant species diversity in a single location and measure the ensuing levels of ecosystem function. Let's further suppose that this experimental protocol was used to evaluate the relationship between plant species diversity and ecosystem function across geographic locations. Such coordinated research could, and indeed often does, reveal different functional relationships in different locations (figure 1.1). At some locations, there could be strong positive relationships between plant species diversity and ecosystem function, as revealed by the steep slope of the regression line. At other locations, flat, almost horizontal lines infer weak if any relationships. Finally, at other locations there could be negative relationships between plant species diversity and function. This leads to a dilemma because we don't know which causal relation to use when making predictions about ecosystem responses to, say, loss of species diversity.
Such an outcome has led to despair that results from experimental ecology are insufficient to make general predictions because the outcomes are entirely context dependent. It is argued that experimentation will never uncover the suite of variables needed to make reliable predictions for all local conditions (Lawton 1999). Instead, it is believed that predictive ability is more likely to come about by combining data from the many study sites and estimating the degree of statistical association between variables of interest (Peters 1986; Lawton 1999). The problem here is that one derives an association, not a causal insight, and so it is merely a "rough" generalization (figure 1.1). Moreover, it is not a meaningful generalization because it abstracts the contingent outcomes among locations. There is no guarantee that, say, boosting plant diversity at any one location will enhance ecosystem function, even though the rough generalization says it ought to. This example illustrates that neither experimental nor meta-analytic approaches necessarily produce predictive insights that can be applied to management if they do not explicitly confront the issue of contingency.
Contingency arises when the nature and strength of ecosystem functioning in different locations are different realizations of the same underlying process. I show in this book how focusing empirical research to explain contingent outcomes can lead to predictive understanding of ecosystem function.
EXPLAINING CONTINGENCY: A WORLDVIEW
I am certainly not the first to suggest that focusing on contingency may help to resolve ecosystem complexity. Both Schoener (1986b) and Simberloff (2004) propose ways to gain understanding of contingency. One way might be to treat contingencies as important case studies, each with their own rich ecological detail (Simberloff 2004). By amassing collections of these case studies one might identify a set of common properties that can guide environmental problem solving and lead to approximate generalizations (Simberloff 2004; see also Shrader-Frechette and McCoy 1993). Another way might be to identify a set of primitive properties or axes representing organismal traits (e.g., species body size distributions, life-cycle characteristics, mobility) and environmental conditions (e.g., environmental severity, trophic structure, resource inputs) and then ordinate systems along the axes (Schoener 1986b). The intent here is to provide some rational ordering of contingency based on fundamental ecological details.
The limitation of both these approaches, as I see it, is that they do not offer a set of rules that enables one to predict how a collection of species with a given set of traits living under a specific set of environmental conditions might fare if they were placed into a new set of environmental conditions. That is, they describe what exists under current environmental conditions but they do not offer a means to predict what may happen as environmental conditions change.
The alternative approach that I present in this book follows from a worldview that-to paraphrase Hutchinson (1965)-considers ecological systems as theaters in which evolutionary ecological acts play themselves out. Such a perspective recognizes that the acts will play themselves out differently in different ecological contexts (theaters), even with identical sets of actors (individuals or species). That is, the act itself is not scripted; it is an improvisation that unfolds differently in different theaters. What this implies is that contingency comes about because of emergent properties of a system; it is a manifestation of the way the act plays itself out in a local theater. To explain contingent outcomes, then, requires understanding the ground rules for the improvisation. This means identifying fundamental rules or fundamental mechanisms, mechanisms that are evident among all systems regardless of spatial extend and temporal scale (Dunham and Beaupre 1998; Petersen et al. 2003; Schmitz 2005b).
Identifying fundamental mechanisms requires identifying ultimate rather than proximate causes of ecological processes that lead to variation across space and time (Mayr 1982). Ultimate explanations, in turn, need to consider the evolutionary ecology of species that comprise ecosystems in order to explain function. This need to link evolutionary and ecosystem ecology to improve prediction has been recognized for some time (Lehman 1986; Oksanen 1988; Levin 1992; Holt 1995; Carpenter and Turner 2000). But, it has been challenging to make the link empirically operational.
To address this challenge, I begin with the universal conception (Paine 1988; Tilman 1989; Cohen, Briand, and Newman 1990) that ecosystems are comprised of species that consume resources and that those consumer species are, in turn, resources for other consumers. From this conception, one can deduce a fundamental rule or mechanism for enacting the play. That is, individuals within a species ought to exhibit flexible adaptive responses to balance fitness gains from foraging against fitness losses related to decreasing the risk of being consumed (Sih 1980; Mangel and Clark 1988; Lima and Dill 1990; Holt 1995; Lima 1998). This fundamental mechanism can transcend spatial and temporal scales, and taxa, but the exact way that the trade-off is balanced will depend on local ecological context (Schmitz 2005b). I illustrate throughout this book how such a fundamental conception has far-reaching implications for explaining the rich ways that consumer-resource (trophic) interactions play themselves out in ecosystems.
CONTINGENCY AND EMERGENCE
By invoking the idea that contingency is an emergent property of ecosystems, I distinguish between weak and strong emergence (Polkinghorne 2005). Weak emergence arises when a whole system property or function emerges as a consequence of causal interactions at a lower level of organization (Polkinghorne 2005). Schoener's (1986b) attempt to synthesize ecological contingency using a suite of basic organismal traits and environmental conditions to characterize system types is an example of the application of the principle of weak emergence. Strong emergence would arise if a new set of causal principles became active in a complex system (Polkinghorne 2005). Strong emergence has been invoked, for example, in explanations of how over the course of the history of life, primitive, competing microorganisms coalesced and forged new synergistic relationships that led to their collective persistence and reproduction-the emergence of individuality (Buss 1987).
Ecologists too have entertained the possibility that ecosystem structure and function is the consequence of strong emergence. Ecology, as originally conceived, focused on individuals of species and their interactions with members of other species and the environment, to build upon the Darwinian view of nature (Haeckel 1866). But, that individual organismic view gave way to studying the properties of ensembles of species as an individual entity-a homeostatic community. This eventually led to the view that species acted synergistically to maintain the structure and function of the whole community, in much the same way that organs in a body contribute to the structure and function of the organism as a whole-the Clementsian view (Clements 1916) of ecological systems (Shrader-Frechette and McCoy 1993; Worster 1994). Tansley (1935) offered forceful and persuasive arguments against this view. The argument held that communities could not be typecast as individuals because the traits and the development processes that gave them their putatively individual character-their species composition-changed among ecological settings, and so they did not remain as homoeostatic entities in space and time.
The distinction between weak and strong emergence also helps to put into some context the ecological maxim that "the whole is greater than the sum of the parts." Many ecologists interpret this to mean that prediction is extremely difficult if not impossible because nonlinearities (nonadditive effects) cause emergent properties that cannot ever be understood by figuring out how the component parts fit together-a strong emergence view. But, consider Tansley's (1935) take on this issue: "I do think a good deal of fuss is being made about very little.... What we observe is juxtaposition and interaction, with the resulting emergence of what we call ... a 'new' entity. And who will be so bold as to say that this new entity, for example the molecule of water and its qualities, would be unpredictable, if we really understood all the properties of hydrogen and oxygen atoms and the forces brought into play in their union? Unpredictable by us with our present knowledge, yes: but theoretically unpredictable, surely not." Tansley essentially argues that we should resist the tendency to invoke strong emergence simply because we do not yet have a good mechanistic understanding of system structure and functioning. That is, the component parts may produce nonadditive outcomes, but those outcomes may still be predictable once we obtain a mechanistic understanding of the way the components interact to produce an effect (e.g., see chapter 6). I use the term mechanistic understanding here in the spirit of Schoener (1986a) and Dunham and Beaupre (1998) to mean the appropriate level of reductionism needed to provide a causal understanding of functional relationships. The crux of the issue here is not that additivity and nonadditivity cause different predictive ability. Rather, it is understanding why the mechanisms of interaction under different contexts lead to additive or nonadditive effects.
PREPARING THE MIND FOR DISCOVERY
Finding the appropriate level of reductionism requires taking the altogether holistic view that ecology is a single discipline that integrates principles from various subfields, including evolutionary, population, community, and ecosystem ecology (Tilman 1989; Levin 1992). It also requires that we actively intertwine theory and empiricism (Kareiva 1989), but not simply for purposes of explicitly testing formal theoretical predictions. Rather, an important value of theory is that it leads to a priori expectations-deductions-that "prepare the mind" (Power, Dietrich, and Sullivan 1998; see also Roughgarden, May, and Levin 1989) to notice phenomena that we otherwise might not if we relied on simple intuition alone.
(Continues...)
Excerpted from Resolving Ecosystem Complexityby Oswald J. Schmitz Copyright © 2010 by Princeton University Press. Excerpted by permission.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.
"About this title" may belong to another edition of this title.
FREE shipping within U.S.A.
Destination, rates & speedsSeller: Better World Books, Mishawaka, IN, U.S.A.
Condition: Very Good. Former library book; may include library markings. Used book that is in excellent condition. May show signs of wear or have minor defects. Seller Inventory # 51264196-6
Quantity: 1 available
Seller: SecondSale, Montgomery, IL, U.S.A.
Condition: Good. Item in good condition. Textbooks may not include supplemental items i.e. CDs, access codes etc. Seller Inventory # 00080449848
Quantity: 2 available
Seller: Books for Life, LAUREL, MD, U.S.A.
Condition: very_good. Book is in very good condition. Clean with little to no signs of wear or markings highlights. Seller Inventory # LFM.6CY6
Quantity: 1 available
Seller: Skihills Books, SUN PRAIRIE, WI, U.S.A.
paperback. Condition: Good. Ex-library with normal markings. Soft cover. Normal cover and page wear. Seller Inventory # 032129
Quantity: 1 available
Seller: Labyrinth Books, Princeton, NJ, U.S.A.
Condition: New. Seller Inventory # 125859
Quantity: 17 available
Seller: GreatBookPrices, Columbia, MD, U.S.A.
Condition: New. Seller Inventory # 4224393-n
Quantity: 1 available
Seller: PBShop.store US, Wood Dale, IL, U.S.A.
PAP. Condition: New. New Book. Shipped from UK. Established seller since 2000. Seller Inventory # WP-9780691128498
Quantity: 1 available
Seller: GreatBookPrices, Columbia, MD, U.S.A.
Condition: As New. Unread book in perfect condition. Seller Inventory # 4224393
Quantity: 1 available
Seller: solisjbooks, Port Kembla, NSW, Australia
Soft cover. Condition: Fine. Seller Inventory # 005018
Quantity: 1 available
Seller: Books Puddle, New York, NY, U.S.A.
Condition: New. pp. 194. Seller Inventory # 263428133
Quantity: 1 available